Book chapters
Typography
  • Smaller Small Medium Big Bigger
  • Default Helvetica Segoe Georgia Times
Jos de Mul. The Game of Life: Narrative and Ludic Identity Formation in Computer Games.  In: Lori Way (ed.), Representations of Internarrative Identity. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.

Representations of Internarrative Identity is based upon Ajit Maan's breakthrough theory of Internarrative Identity, which deals with one's sense of self as expressed in personal narrative, connecting the formation of identity with life experiences. This book is the first extensive examination of the adaptive qualities of Maan's work within diverse areas of scholarship and practice, including cultural studies, gender studies, computer gaming, and veterinary medicine. United by their research application of Maan's theory, these scholars demonstrate the far-reaching implications of Internarrative Identity.



The Game of Life: Narrative and Ludic Identity Formation in Computer Games

Human identity is not a self-contained entity hidden in the depths of our inner selves, but is actively constructed in a social world with the aid of various expressions, such as social roles, rituals, clothes, music, and (life) stories. These expressions not only mediate between us and our world (referentiality) and between us and our fellow man 0communicability), but also between us and ourselves (self-understanding). Consequently, changes in these mediating structures reflect changes in the relationship between us and our world, in our social relationships, and in our self-conception.

In recent decades, the domain of expressions has been (massively) extended by computer games and, as a result, we have witnessed the emergence of a new tool for identity formation. In this chapter, I shall examine the way computer games construct our identity in comparison with traditional narrative media, such as novels and movies. My inves­tigation is primarily philosophical: it aims at a conceptual clarification of the relationship between (playing) computer games and human iden­tity. However, though this study is not empirical, one of its aims is to contribute to the theoretical framework for empirical research in this field. The theoretical starting point of my investigation is Paul Ricoeur's theory of narrative identity. I will argue that this theory provides a fruit­ful conceptual framework for understanding the way in which playing computer games constructs personal identity. However, because his the­ory exclusively focuses on standard linguistic narratives, we will have to amend this theory in order to apply it within the domain of computer games.

I will develop the argument in three sections, starting with a short analysis of the concept of identity. Against this background, I explain Ricoeur's theory of narrative identity and discuss some constraints that prevent its application to computer games. In the next section, after a short analysis of the concepts of play, game, and computer game, I discuss the narrative dimension of computer games and the interac­tive dimension that distinguish computer games fundamentally from narratives. Then I present an outline of a theory of ludic identity and discuss the transformation in our present culture from narrative to ludic identity construction. Finally, I formulate some aspects of this transformation that are crucial for its evaluation.

Narrative identity and its discontents Human

Identity

Like so many words in everyday language, "identity" has no unequiv­ocal meaning, but a number of connotations. This is connected to the long history of the concept, during which the phenomenon of iden­tity has taken on various interpretations. The word has its etymological roots in the Latin concept identitas, which in turn is derived from the concept idem - the same. In the context of our discussion of human identity, it is useful to distinguish among logical, anthropological, and reflective identity.

As a logical concept, "identity" refers predominantly to numerical unity (x = x). Adapted to human beings, the concept of identity indicates the unique relation that every person has with him- or herself. This logi­cal principle of identity means that a person is identical to the self and to no one else. Concerning this personal identity, it is possible to dis­tinguish between physical identity and psychic identity, as a person has both a unique body and - narrowly intertwined with it - a unique mind. In a less strict sense, the concept "identity" is often also used to desig­nate extreme similarity, for example, when we refer to "identical twins." Though identical twins are not numerically identical, they share the same genetic characteristics. However, in common language, the con­cept of "identity" generally not only refers to this rather formal logical notion of identity, but also to the "sameness of essential or generic char­acter in different instances" ("Identity," def. la). In this anthropological meaning, the concept refers to the spatial and temporal continuity of the personality.

Spatial continuity lies in the fact that the elements from which the physical and psychic identity are constructed do not form a loose con­glomerate, but an internal nexus, in which part and whole are closely connected.1 This is already clear on the physical level, where the dif­ferent body parts are integrated into the unity of the body. Thoughts, actions, and desires are linked together in a meaningful way, too. For example, the way an ambitious person visualizes the future is internally connected with bodily and psychic desires and the actions undertaken aim at the realization of these desires. In a healthy person, all aspects of the personality are more or less integrated. Of course, this integration is never complete - human life is characterized by all kinds of dissociative states, such as (day)dreaming, religious or sexual ecstasy, immersion in a movie or a (computer) game, highway hypnosis, intoxication by alco­hol and other drugs, and so on. However, when the meaningful nexus is largely or completely lost - for example in the case of dissociative iden­tity disorders - the result is a disintegration or even a total loss of the person's identity in this spatial sense.

Temporal continuity lies in the fact that in the course of our lives, we remain more or less the same person (i.e., the same spatial unity of bodily and psychic elements). To a certain extent, we keep the same body during our lives, and thanks to memory and expectation, our (con­scious) mind also occupies a certain permanence in time.2 However, this continuity is never complete. Our psychological continuity is character­ized by interruptions (sleep) and gaps (forgetting). Moreover, bodily and psychological continuity is not static; it develops over time from birth to death under the influence of biological growth and renewal (almost all of the cells in the body are gradually replaced by new ones), learn­ing processes, new experiences, and, finally, decay. Also with regard to the temporal nexus, sometimes we see that radical discontinuities - for example, by a complete loss of memory or the loss of a part of the body, a transgender operation, the development of a disruptive addiction, dementia, or a religious or political conversion - may result in funda­mental changes or even total disintegration of the temporal (bodily and psychic) identity.3

A third and crucial aspect of the human identity concerns the reflective dimension of identity. We encounter this dimension when we pose the question for whom the spatial and temporal continuity characteristic of personal and cultural identity arises. Although other people can ascribe a personal or cultural identity to us (which can have a great influence on the way in which we experience ourselves), ultimately we are the ones who experience our own personal (and cultural) identities - that is to say, the meaningful spatial and temporal nexus. Reflectivity denotes self-awareness, self-reflection, having a self-image. We express ourselves and recognize ourselves in self-(re)presentations. Whether someone pos­sesses a female, Muslim, or fan identity (or possibly integrates all three) is not only somewhat arbitrary, determined by physical characteristics, actions, habits, or thoughts, but it is also dependent on whether the per­son regards and recognizes themselves as such. A phenomenon such as transsexuality shows that the objective and the experienced reality do not necessarily correspond.

Narrative identity

In the history of modem philosophy, there has been much discussion about the ontological status of human identity, about its specific mode of being. We can distinguish two extreme positions. On one hand, the rationalist tradition starting with Descartes defined the self or I as a substance with consciousness, "a thing that thinks" (106). Following the Christian notion of the eternal human soul, this tradition conceives of the thinking substance as an isolated, timeless, non-corporeal entity. On the other hand, the more skeptical movement within the empiri­cal tradition, at least starting with Hume, denied the self or I any real substance. According to Hume, consciousness is nothing else than the continuous stream of perceptions and ideas:

I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe anything but the perception... The identity which we ascribe to the mind of man is only a fictitious one. (252, 259)

Or, in the words of Daniel Dennett, a temporary Humean skeptic, it is "a theorist's fiction" comparable with an abstractum such as "the center of gravity" of an object in physics that does not refer to any physical item in the world (see "The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity").

Though the skepticism against the Cartesian conception of the self as a timeless substance is justified, Hume and Dennett seem to throw the baby out with the bathwater. Unlike the case of an entity, which does not have a subjective experience of its center of gravity, a person consciously does experience him- or herself. In the passage quoted from Hume, even he turns out to be someone who claims to be unable to find himself behind the flow of consciousness (Ricoeur, Oneself as Another, 128)! The problem seems to be that both Descartes and Hume seem to agree that the self, if it exists, must be a substance. With the phe- nomenologist Martin Heidegger, however, I want to argue that human existence is distinguished fundamentally from the ontological status of objects such as stones because human beings exist in time and space (see Heidegger, Sein und Zeit,1927). Existing does not simply mean that we are situated in time (after all, this is also true for a stone), but that our being has a fundamentally temporal character. Although we always live in the present, unlike the stone, in our acting, we are always ori­ented toward our future possibilities and we are also always determined by the possibilities we realized in the past. In Oneself as Another, Paul Ricoeur denotes the distinction between the identity of mere occurent entities such as a stone and the identity of human beings by the con­cepts même (idem) and soi-même (ipse), or, in other words, same-identity and se/f-identity, respectively (1-3, 116-117). This concerns the differ­ence between identity as sheer permanence in time and identity as selfness, the personal involvement in, and the reflective consciousness of one's own existence.

According to Ricoeur, the problems flowing from Descartes' concept of identity arise from the very fact that he unfoundedly conceives human identity as a substance. In fact, we are concerned here with a metaphor­ical transfer - intangible human identity is presented as if it were a mere entity like a stone. This metaphorical transfer (and the concep­tual confusion that goes with it) is seductive because the self also has a certain permanence in time because of its bodily and psychological continuity. Therefore, there is a certain overlap of the same and the self. But in these two cases, the permanence in time is of a fundamen­tally different order. As opposed to the stone, the self remaining the same in time - Heidegger calls this "self-constancy" (Selbstständigkeit) (Being and Time: A Translation of Sein und Zeit281) - is not simply continuing to be the same in time, but is the contingent realization of a possibility. Ricoeur clarifies this self-preservation with the exam­ple of an illocutionary act such as making a promise. If one keeps a promise, it is not because one simply remains the same person; it results from a volitional effort. One's identity is not a simple fact, but a continuous task which only ends with death. In everyday existence, individuals are always, as we like to say about our websites, "under construction."

The confusion surrounding the notion of personal identity is further increased by the fact that we have a tendency to identify ourselves with opportunities realized in the past and therefore we seclude ourselves from future opportunities. What at first was simply a possibility takes on the form of an aggregate of character traits and ingrained habits. A "sec­ond nature" emerges that contributes to the continuity of one's personal identity. This fundamental passivity ensures that this much remains the same in us, making us identifiable to ourselves and to others. In this case, there appears to be not so much a question of an overlap, but rather of a transformation of the self to the same. Although this tendency is a natural part of human existence, the degree to which it appears is cultur­ally and historically variable. Although personal (and cultural) identity in traditional societies is generally quite stable, identity is character­ized in modem culture by a high level of flexibility and changeability. As Sherry Turkle notes:

Not so long ago, stability was socially valued and culturally rein­forced. Rigid gender roles, repetitive labor, the expectation of being in one kind of job or remaining in one town over a lifetime, all of these made consistency central to definitions of health. But these sta­ble social worlds have broken down. In our time, health is described in terms of fluidity rather than stability. What matters most now is the ability to adapt and change - to new jobs, new career directions, new gender roles, new technologies. (Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the Internet 255; see also Gergen, The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Society)

It is against the background of the discussion about the ontological sta­tus and the flexabilization of human identity that Ricoeur presents his theory of narrative identity. Ricoeur takes Heidegger's notion of the exis­tential self as his starting point, but he implicitly criticizes Heidegger for sticking to Descartes' immediate positing of the "I." Unlike Descartes and Heidegger, Ricoeur does not believe that we have an immediate access to the self in introspection or phenomenological intuition. Self- knowledge is in almost all cases mediated. We know ourselves only via the indirect route of the cultural expression of ourselves in actions, utter­ances, images, music, nutrition, fashion, housing, institutions, religion, and so on.

Narratives are especially important in this respect. As Roland Barthes states,

The narratives of the world are numberless... Narrative is present in every age, in every place, in every society; it begins with the very his­tory of mankind and there nowhere is or has been a people without narrative... Narrative is international, transhistorical, transcultural: it is simply there, like life itself. (79)

Or, as Hayden White writes, "To raise the question of the nature of nar­rative is to invite reflection on the very nature of culture and, possibly, even on the nature of humanity itself" (1).

This is also the starting point for Ricoeur: "Answering the question 'Who?'... implies the narration of a life story" (Temps et Récit335).4 It is only in the stories we tell others and ourselves about our lives and about (real or fictitious) other lives that we articulate our own selves, and only by identifying ourselves with these stories can one's identity come into being. Thus, for Ricoeur, narrative is not only a suitable metaphor for human identity, but is also preeminently the medium through which we give our identities form. One's identity is contained in one's life story. That story is not pregiven and static, but attains form through one's actions and narrative reflection upon those actions. According to Ricoeur, we can distinguish a threefold mimesis in this process.

The first level, referred to as mimesis1( is connected with the narrative préfiguration of our daily lives. In Ricoeur's view, this lies in the practical knowledge that guides our actions. We experience our dealings with our fellow human beings in terms of meaning: we distinguish motives and interests, we set standards and ascribe values, and we attempt to realize certain ideals in life. Therefore, in a certain sense, our actions already contain an implicit narrative. Our lives are an unremitting "Quest of Narrative," as described by Ricoeur ("Life in the Quest of Narrative")

Ricoeur designates the expression of the experienced prenarrative coherence in explicit narratives (varying from the everyday narratives we tell about ourselves to autobiography and - more generally - in the art of the novel) as mimesisz. This stage is described in dramaturgical terms, derived from Aristotle's analysis of tragedy in his Poetics. Cen­tral to Aristotle's argument is the notion of the plot imythos), which is the expression of a series of mutually connected and motivated actions. According to Ricoeur, the plot (mise en intrigue) can be understood as "a synthesis of the heterogeneous" (Oneself as Another 141). The plot brings the heterogeneous elements of which a story consists - events, such as actions and happenings, and existents, such as settings and characters (see Chatman, Story and Discourse: Narrative Structure in Fic­tion and Film) - to a unity. The Aristotelian plot can be regarded as a complete whole. It is complete because the elements together give the narrative closure. It is whole because all the elements within the plot are linked and there are no elements unrelated to the plot; every ele­ment has meaning in the light of the whole. In a nutshell, the plot has a beginning, a middle, and an end (Aristotle 2:2321). Ricoeur calls this the meaningful configuration created by the plot concordance. However, this concordance is no static state, but is continuously jeopardized by discordances, such as reversals of fortune that threaten the meaningful closure of the narrative. A story is the representation of an act that is continuously frustrated by more or less unforeseen settings and hap­penings. This makes the story a dynamic whole. For that reason, Ricoeur calls the story a discordant concordance (Oneself as Another 141)

The third step in the construction of narrative identity, mimesis3, con­sists of the reflective application of the narrative configuration on the self, resulting in identification with the characters of the story. The unity of the story - the plot - is closely connected to the characters figuring in it. Telling a story is telling who does what and why. We witness how each character develops, and the characters show a dialectic of con­cordance and discordance similar to what is demonstrated in the plot. Contingent events get a narrative coherence through character. From a psychoanalytical point of view, we could say that the identification that characterizes mimesis3 consists in the internalization of the object of desire - the state of concordance obtained by the characters in the story. This is not a simple imitation, but an appropriation or assimila­tion that results in a change in the identity of the identifying person (see Freud 4:156)

However, just as in the case of the plot, the stability obtained by this internalization is rather shaky, as it is continuously confronted by the return of the heterogeneous, which threatens the concordance of our identity. A sublime love, a personal vendetta, a crisis or addiction, illness or death - these are all happenings that give our life story unexpected turns that keep challenging the concordance of the character and ulti­mately may destroy it. Until its very end, the (life) story is characterized by this dialectic between concordance and discordance.

The theory of narrative identity helps us to understand the above- mentioned relationship between the same and the self, and between the self and the other better. The tension between the same and the self turns out to be none other than that between concordance and discordance in our life stories. Every story can be located somewhere between the extremes of stories in which the character simply remains the same (often the case with fairy tales and their stable roles) and stories in which the character completely disintegrates through confrontation with the heterogeneous. Ricoeur mentions Robert Musil's The Man With­out Qualities (Der Mann Ohne Eigenschaften) as a novel in which the self completely loses its identifiable characteristics. Because of the close con­nection between plot and character, it is not surprising that the crisis of the character in this novel corresponds with a crisis of closure in the story. For that reason, The Man Without Qualities perhaps repre­sents the crisis of Western culture in which the grand narratives have lost their persuasiveness (see Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge-, see also de Mul, Romantic Desire in (Post)Modem Art and Philosophy).

The narrative model of identity also throws an elucidating light on the social dimension of human identity. By telling our life stories, we are always already entangled in the dialectics between the self and the other (Ricoeur, Oneself as Another 141). The other is present in differ­ent roles in the stories through which we identify ourselves. In the first place, we identify ourselves with the others that appear in the stories that are being told in our (sub)culture. In the second place, the other is constitutive for our identity because it is always part of our life story, as relative, lover, neighbor, colleague, employer, stranger, enemy, and so on. In the third place, we are always actors in the stories of others. All these dialectical relationships mean that we are continuously entangled in a multiplicity of stories and that our identity, as a result, is a "tissue of stories" (Ricoeur, Temps et Récit356). Just as in the case of George Herbert Mead's account of the self and Turkle's investigation of our identity in the age of the Internet, the self is a multiple self in Ricoeur's theory of narrative identity.

Ricoeur emphasizes the constructive role of literary narratives. But does this not mean that he neglects the difference between life and story? After all, "stories are not lived but told" (Mink 557). Ricoeur argues that it is just because our lives are not stories, because they are unarticulated, poly-interpretable, and without closure, that we need the concordance of stories to control the continuous threat of the heteroge­neous. This confirms that narrative identity is no sheer representation of an already-given entity, but a construction. As this construction is foremost a creation of our imaginations, we can agree with Hume and Dennett that narrative identity is a (literary) fiction, but we should immediately add that it is no theoretical abstract, but a meaningful nexus that we experience and live. One's identity might be called vir­tual in the sense that it is a fiction that creates real effects in our daily lives (see Heim 109-110).

Broadening Ricoeur's theory of narrative identity

I will try to demonstrate later in the chapter that Ricoeur's theory of narrative identity offers a fruitful conceptual framework for an investi­gation of identity formation that takes place in playing computer games. However, first I have to discuss some problems that stand in the way of a successful application of Ricoeur's theory in the domain of computer games. The first problem that I will address has to do with Ricoeur's rather restricted conception of narrativity. The second problem, which I will discuss in the next section, is more fundamental and addresses the question as to whether or not one can approach computer games from a narrative perspective at all

Ricoeur refers to various narratives in the books and articles he has written about his theory, and he uses these in order to develop and illustrate his own ideas about narrative. However, it is striking that he takes hardly any other narratives into account but linguistic ones. It has to be admitted that he is not completely alone in this. Some nar- ratologists hold that narratives only exist in language. Mieke Bal, for example, in the first edition of her Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative, restricts narratives to narrative texts and defines a text as "a finite, structured whole composed of language signs" (5). She further defines a story as "a fabula that is presented in a certain manner" and a fabula as "a series of logically and chronologically related events that are caused or experienced by actors" (5). Moreover, she adds as defin­ing characteristics that in narrative texts, there are always two types of speakers: one that has no specific function in the history narrated, and one that does have such a function (though the narrator and actor can be united in one person). She also states that three levels can always be distinguished with regard to narratives: text, story (which - follow­ing Aristotle and Ricoeur - have been called plot in the foregoing), and history.

However, given this definition of narrative, the restriction of the anal­ysis to linguistic texts is not evident and not even very convincing. It is not clear why a stage play, a dance, or a movie could not count as a nar­rative. As Barthes notes, narrative is a code or form that can be expressed in various media or substances:

Narrative is first and foremost a prodigious variety of genres, them­selves distributed among different substances - as though any mate­rial were fit to receive man's stories. Able to be carried by articulated language, spoken or written, fixed or moving images, gestures, and the ordered mixture of all these substances; narrative is present in myth, legend, fable, tale, novella, epic, history, tragedy, drama, com­edy, mime, painting (think of Carpaccio's Saint Ursula), stained glass windows, cinema, comics, news item, conversation. (79)

For this reason, it is not strange that Bal, in the second edition of her book, broadens the spectrum of her theoretical model to include discussions of visualization and visual narrative, giving various exam­ples from art and film (see Bal, Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative). In this broad conception of narrative, computer games are not in principle excluded from having a narrative dimension and as such play a similar role in identity construction as novels, stage plays, films, and comics do. As we will see in the next section, many computer games, in fact, do have a narrative dimension.

Ricoeur's theory of narrative identity is not only constrained by his exclusive focus on linguistic narratives, but also by the fact that even within this already restricted domain, he hardly takes any other narratives into account other than novels belonging to the modern Western tradition. This is surprising in the light of the fact that with Barthes, narratives are international, transhistorical, and transcultural. In the globalized and multicultural societies that characterize present Western culture, we are increasingly in contact with narrative traditions from other cultures, while immigrants also import and assimilate these traditions in our own culture.

This constraint in Ricoeur's theory should be mentioned because Ricoeur's preference for the classical Western canon is connected with a preference for a specific culturally and historically determined type of narrative that has, as we will see, less in common with the structure of computer games than some of the transcultural narratives that are devel­oping presently in multicultural environments. Though Ricoeur talks about discordant concordance, it is clear that the emphasis is mainly on concordance. In "Life in Quest of Narrative," Ricoeur frankly speaks about "the primacy of concordance over discordance" (22). This primacy also comes to the fore in the interpretations Ricoeur gives of the modern novels by Virginia Woolf, Thomas Mann, and Marcel Proust in Time and Narrative. In his interpretation of Woolf's Mrs. Dalloway, for example, we see that he does not recoil from some interpretative violence. Though the two protagonists in the novel, Clarissa and Septimus, end up in exis­tential crises and suicide because of insoluble conflicts between their personal and public lives, Ricoeur does manage to present the story as representing authentic self-realization in which concordance finally has the last word. Examples such as this show that Ricoeur remains chained to the classical Aristotelian tradition, which is characterized by a desire for closure.

Ajit Maan has argued that Ricoeur seems to presuppose that this Western type of narrative is the universal model for human identity (84). Everything that does not fit in this model would be considered dis- associative at best (57). Maan argues that specific spatial and temporal continuities are not intrinsic characteristics of personal, sexual, ethnic,

or cultural identity, but social and political constructions instead. In her view, "assuming that narrative structure affects action and identity, narrative choice should include not only alternative plots in terms of content but also alternative formal structures" (16). In this context, she discusses the "intemarrative" novel Fault Lines by Meena Alexander. In this novel, Alexander - born in India, raised in Egypt, and now living and working in the United States - gives an account of her life, offer­ing equal rights to the different aspects of her multiple identity. The organizational principle of this novel is not so much temporal continu­ity but rather spatial discontinuity. The result is a heterogeneous fabric with multiple beginnings recurring repeatedly throughout the narrative. As Maan states, "Even the final chapter contains a re-telling of a begin­ning. These beginnings do not lead to a middle. There is no middle that leads to a resolved ending" (45).

This structure, reminiscent of the organizational principle of com­puter games and other hypermedia, prevents certain aspects of her identity from being suppressed or sacrificed to other aspects. Although Alexander describes herself as "homeless, shelterless, with no fixed place to belong, and a blabber of multiple tongues" (177), her narrative is no expression of sheer chaos, but rather an impressive attempt to reconfigure this chaos in a livable nexus (Maan 37).

This experience of contingency and heterogeneity of the migrant could be extended to life in our present postmodern culture, which is being characterized by multiphrenia, "the splitting of the individual into a multiplicity of self-investments" (Gergen 73-74). The concor­dant unifying narrative Ricoeur is talking about is no longer able to express the fragmented identity of the postmodern citizen to which Turkle referred. As Maan argues, new narrative structures might be better capable to express and to make livable the new forms of iden­tity. Perhaps computer games are expressions of these new forms of identity, too.

Computer games: Narrativity and beyond

By broadening Ricoeur’s theory of narrative identity to include nonlin- guistic and nonstandard Western narratives, I hoped to make this theory more suitable for the analysis of identity construction in the playing of computer games. However, according to many theorists in the field of computer games, narratives and computer games are so fundamentally different in their "grammar" that their study requires an essentially dif­ferent conceptual apparatus (see Juul, "Games Telling Stories" 219-226).

In order to be able to judge this critique, we have to compare the ontologies of narratives and computer games.

Play, games, and computer games

It does not seem to be a sheer coincidence that Ludwig Wittgenstein illustrated his notion "family resemblance" with the help of the concept of "game." Just as in the cases of "identity" and "narrative," the concept of "game" does not refer to one essential characteristic, but to a series of similarities and relationships. Card games have some things in common with board games, which in turn have some things in common with ball games. Not all games are amusing, and not all involve winning and losing. What counts as skill and luck varies among them. Even when we restrict ourselves to computer games, we can distinguish various types and genres. However, this does not mean we can give no description of games and computer games.

Games can be regarded as a subclass of play- that is, (mostly) joyful activities that are often temporally and spatially set apart from every­day life. What is merely play is not serious; it has no goal other than itself. However, as Hans-Georg Gadamer notices in his phenomenolog­ical analysis of play in Truth and Method, play has its own, even sacred, seriousness (102). It fulfills its purpose only if the player loses himself in play. Gadamer believes that, "The movement of playing has no goal that would bring it to an end; rather, it renews itself in constant repetition" (102). Most games present the playing person with a task. Moreover, play has its own type of intentionality: we are always playing something (107). However, play is not so much a re-presentation of that something but rather a presentation: "Its mode of being is self-presentation" (108).

When play transforms into structure, it can become either drama (a stage play) or game. In both cases, it gets a specific structure that makes the play into something independent from the player(s). The games have to be played, however, in order to be. The game can therefore - following Johan Huizinga's famous definition - be defined as "a free act that takes place within a specially designated time in a specially desig­nated place, according to specific rules which are strictly adhered to" (13). Like play, games present the players with a specific task, often in a competition. The outcome of the game depends on the actions of the player(s).

Often in play and games, we use attributes such as balls or cards. Computer games distinguish themselves from other games by their technological mediation (see Neitzel, "Narrativity in Computer Games" 227-249). In the case of computer games, the distinctive game space is a virtual space, which can be manipulated with the help of various input devices (mouse, joystick, and so on), of which the effects can be viewed on an output device (monitor). The visual component gives the computer game player the possibility of continuously observing the results of the action. It is, as Britta Neitzel defines it, "a process of self­observation with continuous feedback." This distinction between the point of action and the point of view enables the player to reflect upon the self as another - as the avatar. Another aspect Neitzel points out is that computer games as we know them represent action in which humans can participate. Although this may not be true for puzzles (Tetris) and simulations (Sim Life), it is for most action and fighting games (Tomb Raider), adventures (Alice), role-playing games (Final Fantasy Mys­tic Quest), sports games (Formula 1), and strategy games (Civilization). As Neitzel justly notes, it is this connectedness of the level of action to the level of representation that links computer games to narratives, as these are representations of real or fictional chains of actions as well.

The narrative dimension of computer games

We can formulate the following minimal definition of a narrative: It is the representation of a series of logically and chronologically related events in a specific setting, with a beginning, a middle, and an end, caused or undertaken by actors. The closure that characterizes most sto­ries, as first described by Tzvetan Todorov, is connected with the fact that they represent a transformation in which (1) a state of equilibrium at the outset is (2) disrupted by some event (action or happening), (3) the recognition of this disruption by the (main) character, followed by (4) an attempt to repair the disruption, and finally (5) the reinstatement of the initial equilibrium (Branigan 4). In this narrative scheme, we rec­ognize Ricoeur's dialectics between concordance and disconcordance. At first glance, this description is also applicable to many computer games. Most of these games have this kind of quest structure - desig­nated by Frye as the master genre of the romance (see Frye, Anatomy of Criticism: Four Essays) - in which the protagonists undergo a series of tri­als in order to achieve their goal. Moreover, in many games, we also find existents (characters and settings) and events (happenings and actions).

Let us take as representative example of a standard third-person action game, Enter the Matrix (2003). As in the movie The Matrix Reloaded (2003), on which the game is based, the initial state of equilibrium - man ruling the world - is disturbed by machines taking control and attempting to destroy the human population. The task of the characters in the game (Niobe and Ghost, two side characters in the movie who are acting within settings based upon locations from the movie) is to reinstate the initial equilibrium. It opens with the character or avatar of your choice - Niobe or Ghost (with their respective skills and subtasks) - in a post office, trying to open a specific post office box to retrieve some information. As you make your way through the game, you have to chase airplanes, rescue captured rebels, navigate through a sewer sys­tem, destroy a nuclear power plant, and fight off a sentinel attack from aboard your hovercraft, the Logos.

As Juul has argued, the story is in a sense external to the playing of the game itself in these kinds of narrative games - provided in advance or in breaks between the playing, written on the package, in the man­ual or in introductory and transition movie sequences - and as the ideal story the player has to realize ("Games Telling Stories" 219-226). But the actual playing is not narrative. In fact, computer games such as Enter the Matrix - which is representative of the mainstream of action and fight­ing games, adventures, role-playing games, sports games, and strategy games - show that these games, in fact, are a hybrid combination, and not so much an integration of game and narrative.5 It is true that a nar­rative unfolds, but this does not occur in the game itself. Of course, this is not to say that these kinds of hybrids are a failure. The great success demonstrated by many of these games is that you can add narrative ele­ments in a creative manner without spoiling the game. The narrative framework in which the game elements are presented even enhance the pleasure of playing the game. For fans of the Matrix movie trilogy, the narrative context will enhance the pleasure of playing the game,6 also offering the modes of identification by the reflective application of the narrative configuration on the self, as discussed earlier.

However, this does not yet elucidate the distinctive contribution of the computer game elements to identity construction. In order to ana­lyze this contribution, we have to focus on the aspects of the computer game that do not overlap with narrative. This is where we are not concerned with the point of view of the player, but with his point of (interaction.

Computer games versus narratives: Interaction versus interpretation

If there is one single characteristic that distinguishes (computer) games from narratives, it must be (inter)action. Whereas the reader (or viewer) of a narrative is presented with a chain of events imagined by the author (or director) of the story, the chain of events in the computer game is the result of the player’s action. This is not to say that the reader is a passive consumer of the story; the reader plays a double role with regard to the reading of narratives, occupying at the same time a passive point of view and an active point of interpretation. As has become a standard presup­position in narratology, a story only comes into being when the reader actively constructs it by interpreting the narrative elements and link­ing them to each other. In this sense, readers have a certain freedom of interpretation and different readers can read different stories, depending on their foreknowledge. However, with the exception of certain avant- garde texts such as Julio Cortazar's Hopscotch (see de Mul, "The Work of Art in the Age of Digital Reproduction. Some Remarks on the Transfor­mation of the Avant-Garde" 68-80), the order of the elements or lexia in the case of narratives is determined by the author and not by the reader. In computer games, on the other hand, the player is (interactive in the sense that he or she determines the sequence of the elements that appear on the monitor.

A narrative is linear and the elements of the narrative are linked together by a narrative causality. Narrative speaks the language of fate; every action and event is caused by the preceding actions and motives. It is thanks to this specific chain of actions and events that a narrative in a book can be translated into a film. Both media share the same nar­rative grammar. Conversely, a game player has relatively great freedom to determine the sequence of actions himself. The game, therefore, is nec­essarily multilinear; if the player cannot choose between various options, there is no game at all.

Of course, the freedom of the player is not absolute. Like every game, there is a set of rules that determine which actions can be under­taken and which cannot. In this context, the distinction Michael Joyce makes between exploratory and constructive hypertexts can be applied to games (42). Explorative games are games in which the nature and the number of lexia are fixed and the freedom of the player is restricted to the sequence in which they are presented during the game. In the case of constructive games, however, the player is able to change the nature and number of lexia. We can think of Doom, for example, where players are able to construct their own settings, or of the Star Trek game, which was hacked by players in order to add homosexual characters to the game. These games are versions of what they are becoming, a structure for what does not yet exist. In these cases, there is what Andy Cameron calls real interactivity, "the ability to intervene in a meaningful way within the representation itself, not to read it differently" (33). Cameron elucidates his point by stating that interactivity in music would mean the abil­ity to change the sound, interactivity in painting would allow one to change colors or make marks, and interactivity in film would provide the immersion of the spectator in the scene with the ability to change the way the movie ends. Real activity in computer games is the ability to change the representation and/or rules of the game.

The multilinearity of the game that is connected with its interactivity has important consequences for the temporal and spatial organization of games compared to that of narratives (see Juul, "A Clash Between Game and Narrative"; see also Juul, "Games Telling Stories"). The nar­rative has three temporal levels: the plot (the signifier), the related narrative (the signified), and the reader or viewer. A sequence of shots in a film, lasting only a few minutes, can cover many years of the nar­rative. When watching a film, both plot and narrative are interpreted together by the viewer. Because the times of the plot and the narrative are different, the narrative also has three dimensions of time. It does not only take place at the time of the reading; the plot also presents the past and the future by means of flashbacks and flash-forwards.

Computer games such as Enter the Matrix lack this temporal stratifica­tion. Where the reader or the person watching a film undergoes great temporal mobility by means of flashbacks and flash-forwards, the com­puter game player is inevitably confined to the present. Because he finds himself in an eternal present, he is able to carry out the same actions over and over again. Other than the protagonist of a narrative, who sooner or later inevitably dies, the player is immortal. In Enter the Matrix, every time you are shot dead, you can begin the game again.

With regard to spatial organization, the narrative and the game also differ significantly. The situation here, however, is the other way around. In contrast to film, the game has a spatial stratification and three spatial dimensions. Interactivity means that you can go in various directions - to the left or right, forwards or backwards, up or down. Just as there is a difference between the time of the plot (the signifier) and the time of the narrative (the signified), there is a difference between the space of the game interface (the signifier) and the virtual space disclosed by the game (the signified). There is also a third dimension in the game in which both these spaces are interpreted together - that of the player. In contrast, the three spatial dimensions within the narrative implode into a single-dimensional, sequential path that the protagonists tread through the narrative space. Their fate is that they are doomed to wan­der this single path. From the notion of the spatial dimension, the game and the narrative are as chess and a game of chess. The rules of chess enclose a space within which an unlimited number of different games of chess can be played.

We can also illuminate the difference between narrative and game by looking at the relationship between plot and action. The action is moti­vated by the plot in the narrative, whereas the plot is dependent on the action in the computer game. When the player of Enter the Matrix pulls the trigger of his gun at the right moment and shoots the sen­tinel, he can enter the next room where another challenge awaits him. If he shoots too late and is himself shot dead, he changes the plot. The discursive causality here seems to be reversed - the action determines the plot, or seeks for it in vain (Aarseth 78).

When, finally, we look at the "pleasure bonus" that the narrative and computer game respectively offer the reader, viewer, and the player, again we see an important difference. In the classic narrative, the plea­sure lies in the satisfaction it gives to know how the narrative ends. From a psychoanalytical point of view, we should call it an end-pleasure (Freud 7:209; see also de Mul, Romantic Desire in (Post)Modem Art and Philosophy 180-182). When, understood in Aristotelian terms, there is no ending, the reader is frustrated. The game, however, does not have an end. Without doubt one can stop Enter the Matrix after having gone through all levels, but then, in fact, we stop because of the clo­sure of the accompanying narrative. Games that have no (or hardly any) narrative context, such as Tetris, invite us to play again in order to beat our personal record. Of course, after some time we will stop playing the game, for example, because we are exhausted or bored, only to continue our playing later. The lust provided by the computer game is never an end-pleasure but necessarily always remains a fore-pleasure. This is one of the reasons that playing computer games easily leads to addiction. This fore-pleasure is connected with phantoming the rules of the game and improving one's skills in order to improve the personal record.

Ludic identity

Now that I have described the main difference between narrative and computer games, I am able to analyze the implications of this difference for the formation of identity and give a tentative answer to the question of how computer games affect one's personal identity.

Ludic identity formation

In the previous section, we noticed that narratives and games have a number of characteristics in common. The same can be said for the formation of narrative and ludic identity. Like narratives, computer games are expressions that, among other things, play a function in the formation of identity. They are able to do this because both give expression to important aspects of human life that structure our lived experiences, and by doing that, enable the reflective identification with this structure. With regard to the construction of ludic identity, we can discern three stages, which I will call, following Ricoeur's notion of threefold mimesis, playi, play2, and play3.

Play, refers to the ludic préfiguration of daily life. We experience nature and the human world as playful, for example, when we notice the play of light or waves, when we see the play of animals and children, or experience the play of sexual seduction. Everywhere in our world, we experience movements backwards and forwards that renew them­selves in constant repetition. Varying the words of Friedrich Schlegel, we could say that the (computer) games we play are nothing but a remote imitation of the infinite play of the world (Gadamer 105).

The expression of this experienced pre-ludic coherence in (computer) games forms the level of play2. Central here is the set of rules that con­trol the possible movements backwards and forwards and determine a specific play. The result is not so much a causal chain of events, as in nar­rative, but a playing field (Spielraum) that is a space of possible action. This playing field can be regarded as an infinite whole. The game of Tetris, for example, consists of a finite set of existents and constitutive rules that disclose an infinite number of different game sessions. It does not have a closure, but is always fundamentally open to further (renewal of) action. We always want to beat the present high score. Unlike the narrative, which has an ending that is always predetermined (every narrative refers to a story that has already taken place, even when the story is situated in the present), the outcome of a game is fundamentally indeterminate.

In the third stage of the formation of the ludic identity, play3, the player identifies with the space of possibilities disclosed by the game. The field of possible action is reflectively applied to the self. The infinity of possible outcomes, connected with the constitutive rules, is internal­ized. As in the case of the reflective application of the narrative to the self, there is no simple imitation of these rules in the case of ludic iden­tity - they are being appropriated or assimilated and, as a result, change the identity of the player.

As in the case of narrative identity, there is a constant dialectic between concordance and discordance in the construction of ludic iden­tity. Every game can be located somewhere within the continuum of game formats, ranging from games in which every single action of the user increases the number of possibilities, to those games in which those possibilities decrease based upon user responses. Whereas in many action games and adventures that are designed according a "tree of death," with every choice reducing the number of possible outcomes (the initial choice for Niobe or Ghost in Enter the Matrix restricts the number of possible actions, as each of the characters has a distinct set of tasks and skills), simulation games often do increase the number of possible outcomes with every choice made. However, when we com­pare narratives with games in regard to the balance of concordance and discordance, the dominance seems to be the opposite. The predomi­nant tendency within narrative identity is toward an increase of closure and thus concordance (novels such as Robert Musil's The Man With­out Qualities remain an exception), yet in the case of ludic identity, the predominant tendency is toward an increase of openness. In every situ­ation, the ludic self is in search of new possibilities in order to increase the field of possible action. In this sense, the temporal dimension of narrative and games is opposite. Narration, although taking place in the present, aims at an understanding of what has happened in the past; playing, which also takes place in the present, is directed at future possibilities.

In the case of ludic identity, there is an additional dialectic between the self and the other. The other is always present, not only as a player we want to identify ourselves with, but also as opponent or teammate, as enemy or lover; the other presents possibilities for reciprocal and/or collective action. A possible objection could be that life is no game, but we could formulate an analogue answer as Ricoeur did in reply to the critique, that life is no story. Because our lives are not games, not always joyful and full of possibilities, we need games to oppose the continuous threat of closure. Just as in the case of narrative identity, ludic identity is a creation of our imagination that creates real effects in our daily lives.

Growing dominance of ludic identity?

Narrative and ludic identity do not represent alternatives that mutually exclude each other, but are two identity formations that coexist, and are entangled in many ways, in the same manner as stories and games. We perhaps could clarify their relationship a bit further by returning for a moment to Heidegger's analytics of human existence. Earlier I noted that according to Heidegger, existing in time means that in living in the present, we are always oriented toward our future possibilities, while at the same time we are always constrained by the possibilities we have realized in the past. In a concise formula, Heidegger calls man a thrown possibility (geworfene Möglichkeit)(Being and Time: A Translation of Sein und Zeit135). However, our attitudes toward our past and our futurepossibilities are not the same. We interpret and narrate the past, yet we play with and act upon our future projects. Of course, these dimensions are not completely separate. The past is not simply behind us, but con­tinuously effective in our present actions, and in our interpretations, we continuously revise the past. The choices we make in our actions are always grounded in the past. It is for this reason that narratives and games are often narrowly entangled. Though situated in the past, stories can inspire new future possibilities. Though oriented toward the future, games often repeat possibilities from the past. As we already noticed, human beings tend to identify themselves with the choices made in the past and for that reason become less playful as they grow older. However, oriented toward past and future, stories and games are the expressions of two fundamentally different dimensions of human life.

This does not mean, however, that they are always in balance. In Western culture since the age of modernity, there seems to be a grow­ing dominance of the projective dimension of our existence above our thrownness. In the modern era, man understands himself pre­dominantly as a free-acting subject, a Homo volens that shapes life autonomously. Technology has given this autonomous subject increased power to choose and act. The computer game can be regarded as a popular derivate of this modern ideology. In this light, it is no coin­cidence that interactivity became the buzzword in the amusement industry. No less in the computer game than in the "game of life," the modern subject continuously has to make choices. In premodem culture, most choices - your life partner, occupation, or religion - usu­ally were made for you. As a modem subject, you continuously have to choose. Whether it concerns the simple choice between the left or right door in a computer game or the choice of a certain lifestyle, the emphasis is always upon the volitional dimension of our personali­ties. As we already noticed with Turkle, this necessitates flexibility of the self.

Of course, computer games do not cause this change in identity. This transformation of the modem self is a complex process in which, among many other things, social, political, economic, and technological devel­opments play a role.7 However, the massive dissemination of computer games in Western and westernized cultures is certainly part of this com­plex process as well. It demonstrates that in our culture on the level of the existents there has been a major shift from settings to character, and on the level of the events, from happenings to actions. Reflection has shifted gradually from interpretation of meaning to reflective feedback on action.

Without a doubt, this transformation has been partly on the ideolog­ical level only. Modern subjects, following Descartes, regard themselves as autonomous entities, yet this does not mean that they really are autonomous. Modem history is characterized by a stream of happen­ings that demonstrate how many things are still not yet or - in the age of increasing autonomic technologies (see Kelly, Out of Control: The Rise ofNeo-Biological Civilization) - no longer under our control. Even in our computer games, we constantly face the possibility that the game will be over. However, they also promise us that we always can start all over again

Connected with the shift from narrative and interpretation to game and action, we can discern a shift from temporally organized identity to spatially organized identity. Earlier we observed that human identity has these two dimensions. But also in this case there is no eternal - ahis- torical or acultural - balance between these dimensions. In an age where the number of different roles increases so much that some sociologists even talk about a "saturation of the self" (see Gergen, The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Society), the number of activities we are engaged in at the same time increases no less, and, moreover, these roles and activities keep changing continually over time; the spa­tial organization of the many changing aspects of the self becomes more and more important. The personal computer, with its many windows open all the time, is a moving metaphor for the way we try to deal with this change in ourselves; at the same time it seems to be a device that stimulates this change while simultaneously enabling us to cope with it. The same counts for the remote control, with its primary function shift­ing increasingly from merely determining the sequence of the images on the screen to following different channels at the same time. Com­puter games, with their spatial rather than temporal organization, play no less of an important role in this transformation of the self toward, and of one's worldview. The world itself is no longer conceived of from a sheer historical perspective, but rather as a database, a playing field that enables us to (re)configure all kinds of different worlds. The evo­lution of life on Earth is no longer a narrative in the sense that it is a causal chain of events, but rather a database full of genes that can be recombined in an infinite number of possible worlds. Steven Spielberg's Jurassic Park offers a still Active but far from implausible view of this brave new world. Likewise, genetic manipulation, aesthetic surgery, and the like make our bodily and psychic characteristics less and less depen­dent upon narrative fates and increasingly objects of choice. Again, this view has a strong ideological dimension, so we may expect that stories about what went wrong will also continue to be told. Our future selves probably will remain a more or less hybrid mix of narrative and ludic identities. But as we have seen in the discussion of Alexander's internarrative novel, even these narratives are gradually becoming more spatial in their organization and structure. The historical consciousness that has emerged in the last few centuries, and from which the art of the novel also sprouted, will at least be contrasted with a spatial conscious­ness that does not think in terms of past decisions but rather in terms of parallel possibilities.

Three pedagogical afterthoughts

In the previous sections, I have mainly restricted myself to an exposition of the (partial) transformation of narrative identity into ludic identity that, in my view, can be discerned in our present culture and in which computer games play - already for quantitative reasons - an increasingly important role. As I believe it is important to understand before one judges, I have tried to postpone an evaluation of this transformation. Though it is not my intention to give a comprehensive evaluation in this last subsection (it is for the reader to judge), I do want to provide three pedagogical afterthoughts about some aspects of the process described that, at least in my view, may be important for further evaluation.

First, it is important to keep in mind that computer games are not "just games," but play a constitutive role in cognitive development and in the construction of identity. This role may even be more fundamen­tal than in the case of narratives because the emotional involvement in computer games is very strong. Some decades ago, Sherry Turkle explained that this is connected to the fact that computer games are about action:

When you play a video game you enter into the world of the pro­grammers who made it. You have to do more than identify with a character on the screen. You must act for it. Identification through action has a special kind of hold. Like playing a sport, it puts people into a highly focused and highly charged state of mind. For many people, what is being pursued in the video game is not just a score, but an altered state. (83)

For that reason, the exposure to possible undesirable contents of com­puter games (such as violence, sexism, or racism; see Herz 183), might be more intense than in the case of narratives. However, this does not already imply a negative effect, because in case playing violent games has a positive effect of catharsis, this may be for that very reason stronger than in the case of reading violent novels or watching violent movies. Anyway, we should not forget that computer games are ontological machines in the sense that they, like narratives, not only structure one's (concept of the) world, but also (the concept of) the self.

Connected with the strong involvement in computer games is the danger of addiction. This danger is reinforced by the fact that because of the predominantly fore-pleasure-oriented satisfaction of computer games, they already have an inherent stimulus to repetition. More in general, computer games are part of a technological world that has a strong addictive character as a whole. The modern ideology of makabil- ity results in a heavy dependence on technological means, independent of their success. However, as serious as an addiction may be, we should not exaggerate this danger in the case of computer games. In my opinion, an addiction to computer games is closer to a passion for read­ing novels or watching movies than an addiction to alcohol or crack cocaine. Reading stories, watching movies, and playing games are activ­ities that are not instrumental but rather are goals in and of themselves. They share this feature with forms of addiction to alcohol and other drugs. However, as the latter forms of addiction can ruin one's life, the opposite is the case for those passionate about narratives and games. That narratives and games take place in a time and space beyond the seriousness of everyday life does not mean that they have no value. Insofar as they are ontological tools that sharpen our imaginations and enable us to construct new images of ourselves and the world, it is not easy to exaggerate their value in our lives. Because of its long history and respectable status, not many people are inclined to designate a passion for literature as an addiction, and movies have emancipated themselves in a relatively short time from a fairground attraction to an art form comparable to literature. We value novels and movies, although we know that many trivial novels and cheap movies do not fulfill the onto­logical promise of great art. I would not be surprised if computer games follow the same path so that in the future, in the midst of an ocean of game pulp, we will encounter wonderful games that will disclose new worlds and new modes of self-realization for players.

Finally, if there is a danger connected to computer games, it will not so much lie in the depiction of violence or other undesired behavior, nor in the addictive qualities of these games, but in the impact they might have on human-world openness. In the previous section, I referred to Heidegger’s definition of human existence as thrown possibility. Having such possibilities requires the more fundamental prospect of disclosing a world. By "world," Heidegger means the all-governing expanse of an open relational context (Poetry, Language, Thought 42). This means that even within a strict finite world, an infinite number of relations can be disclosed. As human beings, we not only exist in time, but also in space. We are not simply in space (as the stone is in space), but we continuously discover and establish geographical space as well as room to move and imagine (Being and Time: A Translation ofSein und Zeit 96-97).

However, in many - and perhaps most - computer games today (espe­cially those that are sheer exploratory instead of constructive games), the freedom to move is rather restricted, as the field of possibilities itself is preprogrammed and finite. When we identify ourselves with the help of these impoverished expressions, we impoverish ourselves. Although written more than ten years ago - a long time, given the short history of computer games - the following warning of Eugene Provenzo is still topical:

Bettelheim has pointed to the fact that children, as well as adults, need "plenty of what in German is called Spielraum. Now Spielraum is not primarily 'a room to play in.' While the word also means that, its primary meaning is 'free scope, plenty of room' to move not only one’s elbows but also one's mind, to experiment with things and ideas at one's leisure, or, to put it colloquially, to toy with ideas." Video games such as Nintendo, with their preprogrammed charac­ters and their media-saturated images, present almost no opportu­nity to experiment or toy with ideas... Compared to the worlds of imagination provided by play with dolls and blocks, games such as reviewed in this chapter [Provenzo is referring to a series of Nintendo games] ultimately represent impoverished cultural and sensory environments for the child. (93, 95)

In The Republic, Plato banned narrative because in his view the artists have a bad influence on their audiences. If he had lived now, he might have made the same conclusion for computer games. In both cases, the argument overlooks the fact that we derive our very identities from these expressions. One's humanity is closely linked to the gift of narration and play. Being, in principle, programmable by the player, computer games can help and even inspire us to disclose new worlds and dimensions of the self. Therefore, it would be precarious to condemn them as bad influ­ences. It is wise, however, to keep distinguishing the ones that enrich ourselves and our worlds from those that threaten to impoverish them.

Acknowledgements: This text originally appeared in Handbook of Com­puter Game Studies byjoost Raessens and Jeffrey H. Goldstein, eds., pages 251-66. © 2005 Massachusetts Institute of Technology, reprinted by permission of The MIT Press.

Notes

  1. This idea is especially developed in the hermeneutical and structuralist tra­dition in philosophy and psychology. The German founder of the human sciences Wilhelm Dilthey, introduced the notion of a "nexus of life" (Zusammenhang des Lebens) in which the intellectual, voli­tional, and emotional dimensions are structurally integrated. For a more detailed exposition of Dilthey's hermeneutics, see my The Tragedy ofFinitude: Wilhelm Dilthey's Hermeneutics of Life. For an exposition of the structuralist theory of cognitive structure and development and its relationship to the hermeneutical conception, see van Haaften et al., Philosophy of Development: Reconstructing the Foundations of Human Development and Education.
  2. In the Anglo-Saxon tradition since Locke, this temporal continuity and the implied role of memory is central in the theory of personal identity. In his An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke states that memory is determinate for our identity: "For, since consciousness always accompanies thinking, and it is that, which makes every one [sic] to be what he calls self, and thereby distinguishes himself from all other thinking things, in this alone consists personal iden­tity, i.e. the sameness of rational being: and as far as consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person." (335)
  3. Although the emphasis in this chapter is on personal identity, we can also distinguish these spatial and temporal dimensions (as well as the types of dis­continuity mentioned) with regard to the identity of groups or cultures. A culture is not a loose conglomerate of elements, but shows a certain nexus. A specific subculture, such as that of fans, has a more or less coherent set of language, history, patterns of behavior, and institutions shared by members of this culture. Because this unity of traditions and habits demonstrates a his­torical tenacity, here, too, it can be said that there is a temporal continuity. Personal identity never can be isolated from belonging to a certain group or culture. A fan derives identity at least partly from belonging to the subculture of fans. Moreover, personal identity for an important part appears in social intercourse and communication: "We carry on a whole series of different relationships to different people. We are one thing to one man and another thing to another. There are parts of the self which exist only for the self in relationship to itself. We divide up in all sorts of different selves with reference to our acquaintances. We dis­cuss politics with one and religion with another. There are all sorts of different selves answering to all sorts of different social reactions. It is social process itself that is responsible for the appearance of the self; it is not there as self apart from this type of experience." (Mead and Morris 142). In the discussion of the theories of narrative and ludic identity in the follow­ing sections, we will notice again that personal identity cannot be isolated from this social dimension.
  4. Kevin J. Vanhoozer calls this Ricoeur's "narrative correction of the descrip­tion of Dasein's temporality" (45). In this respect, Ricoeur rather takes Hegel's metaphysics of mediation as his source of inspiration, as well as the hermeneutical transformation of this metaphysics by Wilhelm Dilthey. Ricoeur repeatedly refers to Dilthey's aforementioned notion of the "nexus of life" (Zusammenhang des Lebens),connecting it with the idea that the understanding (Verstehen) of the nexus of our lived experiences (Erlebnisse) is only possible via the detour of the expressions (Ausdrücke)de Mul, The Tragedy ofFinitude: Dilthey's Hermeneutics of Life 225-263).
  5. That we are confronted here with a fundamental difference becomes clear when we think about the fact that it is impossible to translate narratives in games, whereas it is possible to translate the story of a book into a movie or a play (Brooks 3-4). Games will only be recognized as being based on a book or movie if additional narrative context is provided. The fighting scenes in Enter the Matrix are only recognizable as a translation of a part of the story of The Matrix Reloaded because of the narrative setting and characters derived from the movie, not because of the game action as such.
  6. It should be added, however, that the nanative element reduces the game’s repeatability. Unlike puzzle games such as Tetris, if you know the end of the story of the adventure game, then repeatedly playing the game loses its appeal (see Juul, "A Clash Between Game and Narrative").
  7. "Technology does not determine society: it embodies it. But neither does soci­ety determine technological innovation: it uses it" (Castells 5; see also Hughes, "Technological Momentum").

Works cited

Aarseth, Espen. "Nonlinearity and Literary Theory." Hyper/Text/Theory. Ed. George P. Landow. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1994. 51-86.

Alexander, Meena. Fault Lines: A Memoir. New York: Feminist at the City University of New York, 1993.

Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1984.

Bal, Mieke. Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative. 2nd ed. Toronto: University of Toronto, 1997.

--- . Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative. Toronto: University of Toronto, 1985. 

Barthes, Roland. "Introduction to the Structural Analysis of Narratives." Image, Music, Text. Trans. Stephen Heath. London: Fontana Paperbacks, 1982. 79-124. 

Branigan, Edward. Narrative Comprehension and Film. London: Routledge, 1992. 

Brooks, Peter. Reading for the Plot: Design and Intention in Narrative. New York: A.A. Knopf, 1984. 

Cameron, Andy. "Dissimulations: The Illusion of Interactivity." Millennium Film Journal 28.Spring (1995): 33-47. Web. 22 February 2013.

Castells, Manuel. The Information Age: Economy, Society and Culture. The Rise of the Network Society. Vol. I. Massachusetts (Mass.): Blackwell, 1996. 

Chatman, Seymour Benjamin. Story and Discourse: Narrative Structure in Fiction and Film. Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 1978.

Cortâzar, Julio. Hopscotch. New York: Pantheon, 1987. Print, de Mul, Jos. Romantic Desire in (Post)Modem Art and Philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York, 1999. 

--------- . The Tragedy ofFinitude: Dilthey's Hermeneutics of Life. New Haven: Yale UP, 2004. 

--------- . “The Work of Art in the Age of Digital Reproduction. Some Remarks on the Transformation of the Avant-Garde." Art, Life and Culture. Ed. B.-N. Oh. Seoul, Korea: Korean Society of Aesthetics & Institute for Arts and Culture Research, College of Humanities, Seoul National University, 2000. 59-80. Print. Dennett, Daniel. "The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity." Tufts University Cen­ter for Cognitive Studies, n.d. Web. 30 July 2013. http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/ papers/selfctr.htm.

Descartes, René. Discourse on Method and the Meditations. Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, 1968. 

Freud, Sigmund. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Ed. James Strachey, Anna Freud, Carrie Lee Rothgeb, and Angela Richards. London: Hogarth, 1953.

Frye, Northrop. Anatomy of Criticism: Four Essays. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1957.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Truth and Method. 2nd rev. ed. New York: Crossroads, 1989. 

Gergen, Kenneth. The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Society. New York: Basic, 1991. 

Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time: A Translation of Sein und Zeit. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. Albany, NY: State University of New York, 1996. 

--------- . Poetry, Language, Thought. New York: Harper & Row, 1975.

Heim, Michael. The Metaphysics of Virtual Reality. New York: Oxford UP, 1993. 

Herz, Jessie Cameron. Joystick Nation: How Videogames Ate Our Quarters, Won Our Hearts, and Rewired Our Minds. Boston: Little, Brown, and, 1997. 

Hughes, Thomas. "Technological Momentum." Does Technology Drive History?: The Dilemma of Technological Determinism. By Merritt Roe Smith and Leo Marx. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 1994. 101-113. 

Huizinga, Johan. Homo Ludens: A Study of the Play Element in Culture. New York: J & J Harper Editions, 1970. 

Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the Exper­imental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects. London: Everyman's Library, 1956. 

"Identity." Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Web. N.d. 22 February 2013.

Joyce, Michael. Of Two Minds: Hypertext Pedagogy and Poetics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan, 1995. Print.

Juul, Jesper. "A Clash Between Game and Narrative." A Clash Between Game and Narrative. Jesper Juul, 17 April 2001. Web. 22 February 2013.

--------- . "Games Telling Stories." Handbook of Computer Game Studies. By Joost

Raessens and Jeffrey H. Goldstein. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2005. 219-226. Print. Kelly, Kevin. Out of Control: The Rise of Neo-Biological Civilization. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1994. 

Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon, 1975.

Lyotard, Jean-François. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1984. 

Maan, Ajit K. Intemarrative Identity. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1999. 

Mead, George Herbert and Charles W. Morris. Mind, Self & Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago, 1934. 

Mink, Louis. "History and Fiction as Modes of Comprehension." New Literary History 1 (1970): 541-558. Print.

Musil, Robert. The Man Without Qualities(Der Mann Ohne Eigenschaften). Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1952. Print.

Neitzel, Britta. "Narrativity in Computer Games." Handbook of Computer Game Studies. By Joost Raessens and Jeffrey H. Goldstein. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2005. 227-249. Print.

Provenzo, Eugene F. Video Kids: Making Sense of Nintendo. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1991. 

Raessens, Joost and Jeffrey H. Goldstein. Handbook of Computer Game Studies. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2005. 

Ricoeur, Paul. "Life in the Quest of Narrative." On Paul Ricoeur: Narrative and Interpretation. Ed. David Wood. London: Routledge, 1991. 20-33.

--------- . "Narrative Identity." On Paul Ricoeur: Narrative and Interpretation. Ed. David Wood. London: Routledge, 1991. 188-199.

--------- . Oneself as Another. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1992.

--------- . Temps et Récit.Vol. III. Paris: Ed. Du Seuil, 1985.

Turkle, Sherry. Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the Internet. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995. 

--------- . The Second Self: Computers and the Human Spirit. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1984. 

Van Haaften, A. W., Michiel Korthals, and Thomas E. Wren, Eds. Philoso­phy of Development: Reconstructing the Foundations of Human Development and Education. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1997.

Vanhoozer, Kevin. "Philosophical Antecedents to Ricoeur's Time and Narra­tive." On Paul Ricoeur: Narrative and Interpretation. Ed. David Wood. London: Routledge, 1991. 34-54. 

White, Hayden. "The Value of Narrativity in the Representation of Reality." On Narrative. Ed. W. J. T. Mitchell. Chicago: University of Chicago, 1980.1-33.

News

This website is currently under (re)construction

Books by Jos de Mul

Search this website

Contact information